Equality beyond dignity: Multi-dimensional equality and Justice Langa’s judgments

Equality beyond dignity: Multi-dimensional equality and Justice Langa’s judgments

Authors Catherine Albertyn, Sandra Fredman

ISSN: 1996-2088
Affiliations: Professor of Law, University of the Witwatersrand, Johannesburg; Attorney in the High Court of South Africa; Rhodes Professor of Laws of the British Commonwealth and the United States, University of Oxford
Source: Acta Juridica, 2015, p. 430 – 455

Abstract

The tendency for South African equality jurisprudence to reduce equality to a single value, namely dignity, has been much debated, especially around the relationship of dignity to disadvantage. In this article we argue for a multidimensional idea of equality that moves beyond a dignity/disadvantage paradigm to enable a fuller exploration of the complex harms and injuries that underlie equality claims, and greater elucidation of the multiple principles and purposes of equality. In particular, we argue that substantive equality should be understood in terms of a four-dimensional framework, which aims at addressing stigma, stereotyping, prejudice and violence; redressing socio-economic disadvantage; facilitating participation; and valuing and accommodating difference through structural change. We suggest that this enables a better exploration of the different principles that underlie equality and an open discussion of complementarities and tensions between them. We explore the benefits of this approach through an evaluation of three equality cases in which Justice Langa delivered the leading judgments. Although we do not claim that he fully adopted such an approach, we engage Justice Langa’s philosophy on equality as it emerges from these judgments, and evaluate the extent to which we can develop from this a more fully-fledged understanding of equality and its underlying values in the South African Constitution.

Constitutional protection of the right to privacy: The contribution of Chief Justice Langa to the law of search and seizure

Constitutional protection of the right to privacy: The contribution of Chief Justice Langa to the law of search and seizure

Authors Chuks Okpaluba

ISSN: 1996-2088
Affiliations: Adjunct Professor of Law, University of Fort Hare
Source: Acta Juridica, 2015, p. 407 – 429

Abstract

The right to privacy in s 14 of the Constitution includes the right not to have one’s person or home searched, one’s property searched, one’s possessions seized, or the privacy of one’s communications infringed. Chief Justice Langa wrote two landmark judgments of the Constitutional Court concerning constitutional protection of privacy in the context of search and seizure operations: Investigating Directorate: Serious Economic Offences v Hyundai Motors Distributors (Pty) Ltd concerning the constitutional validity of statutory provisions authorising the issue of search warrants to investigate serious crimes, and Thint (Pty) Ltd v National Director of Public Prosecutions; Zuma and Another v National Director of Public Prosecutions, concerning the constitutional validity of applications for search warrants, their terms, and the manner of their execution. This contribution explains the significance of these judgments, placing them in the context of the common law and the Constitution’s protection of privacy more generally. In the final analysis, it becomes clear that Chief Justice Langa’s contributions to this branch of the law were enormous and his erudition epitomised clarity.

On the reciprocal relationship between the rule of law and civil society

On the reciprocal relationship between the rule of law and civil society

Authors Stu Woolman

ISSN: 1996-2088
Affiliations: Professor of Law and Elizabeth Bradley Chair of Ethics, Governance and Sustainable Development, University of the Witwatersrand, Johannesburg
Source: Acta Juridica, 2015, p. 374 – 406

Abstract

And I’m driving a stolen car, down on Eldridge Avenue. Each night I wait to get caught, but I never do. She asked if I remembered the letters I wrote, when our love was young and bold. She said last night she read those letters: and they made her feel one hundred years old. I’m driving a stolen car, on a pitch black night, and I’m telling myself — I’m gonna be alright. But I ride by night, and I travel in fear, that in this darkness, I will disappear. Bruce Springsteen ‘Stolen Car’ The River

Can we discard the doctrine of legal guilt?

Can we discard the doctrine of legal guilt?

Authors Pamela-Jane Schwikkard

ISSN: 1996-2088
Affiliations: Dean of the Faculty of Law, University of Cape Town
Source: Acta Juridica, 2015, p. 360 – 373

Abstract

The doctrine of legal guilt enjoys little popular support and there are systemic breaches of this doctrine in the criminal justice system. These breaches only occasionally attract public approbation and due process is frequently blamed in both popular and political discourse for the government’s inability significantly to reduce South Africa’s high crime rate. I argue that despite the unpopularity of the doctrine it would be dangerous and futile to discard it for short-term political gains.

S v Williams: A springboard for further debate about corporal punishment

S v Williams: A springboard for further debate about corporal punishment

Authors Ann Skelton

ISSN: 1996-2088
Affiliations: Professor and Director of the Centre for Child Law, University of Pretoria
Source: Acta Juridica, 2015, p. 336 – 359

Abstract

In an early judgment of the Constitutional Court, S v Williams, Justice Langa found that judicial whippings were unconstitutional because they violated young offenders’ rights to dignity and humane treatment. Former Chief Justice Langa was also a member of the unanimous court that found the law prohibiting corporal punishment in schools to be a reasonable and justifiable infringement of their parents’ right to religious freedom. However, s 12 of the South African Constitution guarantees everyone the right to be protected from all forms of violence, either from public or private sources. This contribution considers how the court might deal with a challenge to the constitutionality of the common-law defence of reasonable chastisement, which permits corporal punishment of children by their parents in their own homes.

State liability and accountability

State liability and accountability

Authors Alistair Price

ISSN: 1996-2088
Affiliations: Associate Professor, University of Cape Town; Advocate of the High Court of South Africa
Source: Acta Juridica, 2015, p. 313 – 335

Abstract

This contribution examines the relationship between two intersecting themes in Chief Justice Langa’s judgments: the need to hold the state accountable for its wrongdoing and the need to hold the state liable to pay a monetary sum to a victim of its wrongdoing. I argue that accountability is promoted by requiring the state to explain or to justify its actions and by holding it responsible for its actions. Responsibility for wrongdoing may and should take a variety of forms, both legal and political. Legal liability to pay money is but one of these. There are at least four distinct grounds to hold the state liable in South African law. Our courts have relied most heavily on one of these routes, namely the law of delict. Although in principle this is welcome, in future further attention should be given to the possibility that awarding ‘public law’ compensation as an alternative, whether constitutional damages or an award grounded in administrative law, may on occasion be a better means to hold the state accountable for failures to perform its distinctive obligations.